Famine and Affluence; Fathers and Children

The idea of this piece is to compare the radicalism Turgenev portrays in Fathers and Sons with Peter Singer’s ideas about charity as discussed in his 1972 essay “Famine, Affluence, and Morality”. The comparison is in some sense arbitrary, but I hope to use it to make the claim that what Singer suggests – essentially, that we in the developed world ought to give a large part of our income away to aid those less fortunate than ourselves – is not particularly radical at all, while Bazarov’s “nihilism”, the demand to “deny” everything, to take nothing on faith, remains a call that most of us would struggle to answer.

I am writing this piece in part for myself. The conclusion, that we probably ought to listen to Singer and give a non-trivial amount of our income away to charity, appears to me to be manifestly correct. But at the same time, I am not doing it and do not see myself doing it in the near future. I cannot argue against him – I am not a philosopher and my ability to reason my way out of abstract arguments is limited. But perhaps by throwing down onto the page what I think about him I may find a handhold by which I may begin to pull myself out of the prison cell of my own guilt at my failure not to act.

I will leave you to judge. First, we will summarise Singer, then we’ll go through Turgenev, and finally, we will attempt to bash the two of them together.

Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Peter Singer’s essay was written in 1971, during the Bangladeshi War of Independence. A large part of that country’s population was living and dying in terrible conditions caused by the war. Rich nations were sending aid, but Singer notes that the aid was not substantial. Britain sent little over 5% of the amount it had then spent on developing the Concorde airplane, while Australia’s contribution amounted to less than a twelfth of the cost of the Sydney opera house. Singer denies neither the value of culture nor rapid intercontinental air travel, but he notes that we would probably consider human life more valuable than either of those things. At least in theory.

Singer does not only criticise the response of states. He notes that people have failed too – “people have not given large sum to relief funds; they have not written to their parliamentary representatives demanding increased government assistance; they have not demonstrated in the streets, held symbolic fasts, or done anything else directed toward providing the refugees with the means to satisfy their essential needs.” While there were exceptions, the average citizen’s response was inaction. And the scale of the famine and its coverage in the media meant that inaction could not have been from ignorance.

Singer argues that such inaction is unjustified. His argument in the short essay, which can be read here, is that “if it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it.” He gives the famous example of a drowning child:

“If I am walking past a shallow pond and see a child drowning in it, I ought to wade in and pull the child out. This will mean getting my clothes muddy, but this is insignificant, while the death of the child would presumably be a very bad thing.”

If we agree with the principle about preventing bad things from happening, distance should be of no importance, nor should whether we alone can help or whether many can – either way, we should do something. In centuries past, I would scarce have known about suffering on a different continent, let alone how to avert it. But – and Singer is writing in 1971, recalling – “instant communication and swift transportation have changed the situation.” We may say that we are better able to judge who needs the help when we help those closest to us, such as the local homeless. But even this is a somewhat leaky defence. Experts are able to assess the effectiveness of charities, providing reassurance that our money would be put to good use. We do not need to judge, and in fact, we probably lack the tools to judge as effectively as someone whose work has had them spend years honing their judgement.

What this means is that our excuses are inadequate. This leads Singer on to his next point, namely that we have an idea of charity that is wrong. Western societies think of charity as something extra, rather than as a duty. (Whereas it is one of Islam’s five pillars). Because it is something extra, we do not expect people to do it, though we may praise them if they do. However, if we spend our money on fast cars instead of helping those who are literally dying in ways that could be prevented by that same money, we are – according to the premises of Singer’s argument – in some sense guilty. We should give and take action, and we should condemn those who do neither. Giving is not “supererogatory” – it is not something above and beyond goodness, but a constituent component of goodness itself.

That human beings are selfish is not really a good reason not to accept the argument. That nobody else gives is also not a good reason – that is merely a form of cowardice.

And so, Singer draws his rather simple conclusion: “a great change in our way of life is required.” He presents a strong and a weak version of his argument. The former: that we should “prevent bad things from happening unless in doing so we would be sacrificing something of comparable moral significance”, and the latter: “We should prevent bad occurrences unless, to do so, we had to sacrifice something morally significant.” To use an example that has been beaten to death already, the loss of a cup of coffee at one’s local chain is certainly not “something morally significant”. But one could put that money to a good cause and achieve thereby something that truly is morally significant. You know, malaria nets or whatever the charitable flavour-of-the-week is.

In a couple of places, Singer has suggested that giving 5% of our income is a reasonable starting point for answering the question of how much we should give. This is all part of the big Effective Altruism movement and is not worth us fussing over now. For the purposes of this piece, we can summarise Singer’s argument as being that we ought to give more and sacrifice things that do not really matter in comparison with what that money could achieve.

Fathers and Children

Turgenev’s novel, Fathers and Sons, was published in 1862. Russia had suffered a crushing defeat in the Crimean War, with the result that the Empire was taking a long look at itself. The serfs were emancipated in 1861, but with terms that left them still very much shackled to their old masters. Localised revolts caused by peasants who could not read and had been too optimistic in their interpretation of the Tsar’s proclamation were punished with the usual state-sanctioned murder. At the same time, angry with the government’s unwillingness to take further steps to advance Russia into at least the 18th century, young men – and women – became increasingly radicalised. In the same year that the serfs were emancipated the Land and Liberty League was founded, whose most famous act was the murder of the chief of police. Tsar Alexander II himself, who had started his reign with such reforming vigour and then very quickly forgotten all about it, would be blown to pieces a few years after that.

This is all after the novel’s publication, but the best literature tends to identify nascent themes of an age before they become generally apparent, and Fathers and Sons is no exception. It dramatizes a shift in the idea of progressive politics between the older generation, particularly in the figure of Pavel Kirsanov, and the younger, in the figure of Bazarov. The book’s original epigraph gives an idea of the shift we are dealing with:

“Young Man to Middle-Aged Man: “You had content but no force.” Middle-Aged Man to Young Man: “And you have force but no content” – From a contemporary conversation

The older generation in real life had such illustrious figures as Alexander Herzen, whom I’ve written about previously, but it managed to achieve precious little in practice. The new generation was impatient and wanted change now. The anarchist Bakunin (famous phrase, “a destructive urge is also a creative one”) was the most famous member of the older generation to “cross-over”. The young people themselves do not provide many heroic examples. The first one who comes to mind is Sergei Nechaev, who is the model for Pyotr Verkhovensky in Dostoevsky’s Demons, having murdered an innocent man for the sake of trying to improve his revolutionary cell’s cohesion (it did not work).

Pavel Kirsanov, like Dmitry Rudin in Turgenev’s earlier novel of that name, was something of a revolutionary in his youth – both of them fought at the barricades in a France witnessing a revolution. Such action is, funnily enough, reactionary, or at least reactive. They joined a revolution, rather than trying to foment it. The narodniki (this later generation) actually went around the peasants, attempting to stir them into revolt. In practice, the peasants were just as conservative as the Tsars, and most attempts at getting them to revolt failed. Alexander Etkind has noted that the young revolutionaries often followed a particular pattern – “fascination with texts led to fascination with sects; disillusionment with sects led to violence”. Young men from seminaries saw Russia’s long tradition of religious dissent as being the secret to organising political dissent, not realising that the sects simply wanted to be left alone. Disillusioned, they turned to violence.

Within the novel, Bazarov enacts “going to the people”, as it was later called, in miniature. He speaks to the peasants on the Kirsanov estate, where much of the story takes place. But when he actually tries to discuss politics with them, they are bemused and think of him “as a kind of holy fool”. Still, Bazarov’s failure as a revolutionary is not the reason that he has become one of the most well-known characters in Russian literature. Instead, it is his passionately held beliefs that are responsible. He declares that we must deny “everything”. Whereas the other characters are wet and wishy-washy sops who like poetry and music, Bazarov’s language early in the novel is declarative, clear, and forceful.

And what does he suggest, apart from denial? Well, that’s the problem. “We clear the ground”, he says – the most important thing is to destroy. Everything that exists must be subjected to rational criticism as if it is a theory in a book, and if its foundations are unstable, it must be toppled. Religion, the Empire itself – these are things that at that time could certainly have done with a healthy dose of criticism. But Bazarov offers nothing in their place, only the promise that rationality will sort everything out.

Bazarov’s forceful character is in its way inspiring. But that same character disintegrates over the course of Turgenev’s novel. Bazarov falls apart when he falls in love. After all his declarative sentences suddenly it’s all mush with him. And then he dies. Turgenev, who was accused by both conservatives and progressives for his novel, ultimately considered himself a rather boring moderate. “I am, and have always been, a “gradualist”, an old-fashioned liberal in the English dynastic sense, a man expecting reform only from above.” This quote comes from a letter written to a newspaper, but even so, it’s hard to find much in Turgenev’s writing that contradicts it. He dislikes everything that diminishes human life, whether it be authoritarian or radical. But he admires the radicals of the new generation all the same.

Fathers and Sons ends with Bazarov buried and two weddings having taken place. The first of these is between Bazarov’s friend Arkady and Katya, the sister of the woman Bazarov falls in love with; the second is between Arkady’s father and his mistress, a peasant girl. There are few events better reflective of compromise and cohesion than a wedding. Whereas Bazarov’s love for an interesting woman fails, Arkady’s love for a boring girl who gives him an heir is more successful. At the same time, the ending suggests a certain amount of progress, for the second marriage shows that rigid social hierarchies do need to be adjusted from time to time. 

Comparison

We may consider both Singer and Bazarov to present radical ideas, but there is a great difference of degree. Singer asks us to reconsider our idea of duty, whereas Bazarov demands the complete reconfiguration of societies’ fundaments. Although there is an honest desire to improve the lot of the peasant in Bazarov’s views, or at least in the views he is supposed to represent, there is also something horrible. I can’t remember now who said it, and it may be that nobody knows, but one of the nihilists (Pisarev?) once said that a cobbler was worth more than Pushkin. This is blatantly false – it assumes an unbelievably limited view of human nature, one where art has no place. A cobbler is practically valuable, but Pushkin has had a far greater impact than even the best cobbler – he reaches to the soul.

When we go around destroying things, we soon discover that it’s much easier to break than to build. We might agree that religion is generally bad, and most would agree that an Empire is not the best political structure. But we are unlikely to agree about what to replace them with, and Russia’s experience has been that every time they break something, filled with hope, they have replaced it with something worse. Turgenev’s gradualism, as with any gradualism, is something of a cop-out. Martin Luther King Jr’s comments that the greatest enemy of black emancipation is the white moderate are pertinent here. Moderation all-too-easily becomes inaction. And many of the issues people face do cry out for action, not twiddling our thumbs.  

Emotionless Bazarov leads a life that can hardly be called rich. Those emotions that he does have are very much linked to the very structures that he would like to critique – family, love, and so on. I do not think that we cannot love without society, but it would certainly be different, and perhaps not nearly as nice. Perhaps that’s why I found the ending to E.M. Forster’s Maurice so unsatisfying. In that novel, the main character ends up in a relationship with a lower-class man with whom he has nothing in common except their shared homosexuality. This is not a healthy base for a relationship; instead, society needs to be changed so that they can experience full lives within it.

Singer does not say that we need to change society. Or rather, he does not demand the destruction of our values in the same way that Bazarov does. Instead, he asks merely that we readjust our idea of charity and give a little more away. Society, and indeed the world, would be very different if we all started giving to good causes. But our values would not be much changed, though we would almost certainly be better people for it. Bazarov’s ideas retain their radicalism today because they reflect a fundamental impatience to improve things. There are many problems with modern society that I think are in need of urgent redress – wealth inequality, various societal divisions, global warming, mental health, political and institutional distrust, etc etc – but I am not entirely convinced that we are capable of solving them as quickly as their severity demands. Probably we’d make things worse.

Taken over time, everyone giving to charities that actually work to improve people’s lives would actually improve people’s lives. Richer, happier people would build better institutions and feel more engaged in their societies, solving a whole host of problems. Engaging in charitable work will build social cohesion within developed countries too, and deal with some of our own many and varied problems. In short, in a boring way, Singer’s view can be considered gradualist. Our own world is arguably getting better already (I mean discounting climate change and growing wealth inequality, generally we are becoming richer and better educated worldwide). Redistributionist charitable giving (because any giving is redistributional, after all) will only speed things up.

And yet I know that there are Bazarovs among us. One of the main criticisms of Singer’s work is that it reinforces existing systems, rather than proposing new ones. In this view the reason we are all depressed and in unequal circumstances on a burning planet is because our current economic paradigm (capitalism) has brought us to this, and unless we change things up, it will continue to do so. Giving money away doesn’t help this. I am not sure how far I can agree with this view. I like to blame capitalism for everything as much as the next person, but it’s hard to deny the concrete good that charitable giving can achieve. Ideally, we should probably both aim to change the system while supporting people within it.

I myself have an instinctive preference towards local solutions, but it’s hard to defend this view without saying I care more about the people around me than those further away. If we work to engage with the local community, we build strong structures of the sort that can’t quite be quantified – things like trust. We make places better to live in for ourselves and others. And if everyone acted like this, we would all be happier. This is essentially what someone like Wendell Berry is all about. But the difficulty I see with this is that we cannot focus on the local issues without being aware of the global ones. Global news and global charities mean that Pandora’s box has been opened – now we humans have considerably more power, and alas, more responsibility. Too much, in fact, which is why we have failed, and Peter Singer and others yell at us.

Conclusion

Which brings us to the problem. “Famine, Affluence, and Morality” doesn’t really ask that much of us, but it asks more of us than we are probably willing to do. It does not ask us to give up all luxuries (at least the weak form of the argument, which is already asking enough), it still allows us art and music and friendship and fun. But it would deny us much that we have grown used to and think we cannot live without.

A society where we all give, even a little, is clearly a better and more moral society than one where we do not. It is a more responsible one too. We can argue that giving doesn’t work because it doesn’t correctly deal with pernicious systems, or that a local approach is better – but there is one way that we cannot, I think, argue. We cannot say that doing nothing is morally alright. One can try, of course. But it seems that we must, if we are to go to sleep guiltlessly, act.

The things that make life worth living – our friends, our families, our communities, our learning, our experiencing this rich and wondrous world – are not lost by giving. If anything, the loss of excess luxuries, of things we can go without, would only strengthen them all. With fewer distractions we would have a better, more direct, appreciation for friends and partners, have more time for communities and art. It is not a great ask, but at the same time, it is almost impossible. For I am a selfish one: I want to save and invest, I think already about my own descendants, about my own future. I think about all this even though I know I will have a roof over my head whatever happens, whereas the same cannot be said of those who today go to sleep hungry.

I want grand, heroic, solutions – if blowing up a pipeline or two would save the world, I’d be there planting the C4. But I don’t even appear capable of the unflashy and easy solution right in front of me – siphoning off a little of my large-enough pay check.

The world is a mess, but it is our mess, and I am desperately fond of it really. But it can be better. And Singer’s piece offers a clear guide on how to make it so. I cannot despise it for that. We must have things to hope for, and ways of making that hope come to pass.

And perhaps I should be fairer to myself too. All told, I have received my salary twice, and given the job has required me to move abroad, my getting-started expenses have been quite high. Perhaps it’s too early to say whether I will fail to do Singer proud. Time will tell, and one day this blog will shiftily or proudly display the answer.

As for you, readers, how do you sleep at night? Do you give, do you volunteer? If not, what can you say to undermine Singer’s argument?

4 thoughts on “Famine and Affluence; Fathers and Children”

  1. Hi Angus, hope you’re well.
    I hope you don’t mind me encroaching on your blog but you should blame your pesky girlfriend. Quite good timing that I’m reading this during the middle of my poverty and development topic in anthropology, although I feel like the way I think about this topic comes from a very different perspective. The main thing I take away from this is a negative gut reaction to Peter Singer, but perhaps this is because my only knowledge of him up until now is studying euthanasia in A-level philosophy and his idea that parents should be allowed to euthanise disabled babies if they wish to.
    I just feel like from everything I have read within anthropology so far is that all social issues come down to power and social structure. I sometimes feel like the enormous push for charity shifts the blame onto ‘regular’ people who have limited ability to make any real change so long as divisions between the rich and poor exist – although of course it does good in the short term. People of middling incomes can give as much as they want to relieve themselves of guilt, but would this really be necessary if we did not live in a society with such vast inequality? So long as billionaires exist at the top society, so will the millions at the bottom.
    By viewing a certain section of society as ‘the poor’, this creates a category of a voiceless mass who have no option but to receive aid from kindly, morally upright strangers – it feels like we take away their voice or independence, reducing them to beggars rather than people we can relate to as equals.
    I suppose this is why the NGOs I’ve looked at, including the one I’m planning to volunteer for over the summer, always encourage independence and self-sufficiency by encouraging entrepreneurial skills and so called ‘self-empowerment’ rather than economic development alone. However when discussing these ideas with my supervisor it seems that often what these elites contribute to society are more workers who buy into the concept of capitalism and self-reliance, who will nevertheless stay at the bottom of the pyramid – hence why I find that charity often reinforces divisions between the rich and poor rather than contributing to meaningful change – which is why the system of ‘philanthropcapitalsm’ is so problematic to me.
    Maybe the ideas in my recent essay on philanthropy would be of interest to you, although the format is quite different to philosophy (and is also not that great but the ideas are interesting). The further I get though my degree the more cynical I become towards the ideas of development, although I do agree with you that these moral questions are well and good but what ultimately matters is action – but in what form? The idea of needing to give to ‘charity’ as an abstract concept does not seem like enough, but maybe my volunteering will give me some practical knowledge so I can rethink my opinions.
    I enjoyed this post, and hope you are having a good- or at least interesting – time in Russia?
    Audrey

    1. Hi Audrey,

      I think I’ve picked out your objections in turn to respond to, but please let me know if I’ve missed or misunderstood any.

      ‘The enormous push for charity shifts the blame onto ‘regular’ people who have limited ability to make any real change so long as divisions between the rich and poor exist’.

      The point of Singer’s argument, I think, is that there are very few people in the developed world who have no ability to make ‘real change’. Because doing good doesn’t have to mean a complete restructuring of society (independently of whether you want that or not). Doing good could be just improving one person’s life significantly. One example: GiveWell estimates that you on average save a life for $3000 by giving to Helen Keller International to deliver Vitamin A supplements to children that need it. Plenty, if not all, ‘regular people’ could reasonably donate $3000 over a certain period. And that’s only if you’re only looking at lives saved – they reckon $1 is what it costs to give deworming medicine to a child with parasitic worms – and pretty much everybody can afford that.

      If a child was standing next to you, and said, ‘Can I have a dollar to buy the medicine I need?’, would you answer, ‘No, I’m afraid I can’t give money because I have limited ability to make any real change so long as divisions between rich and poor exist.’ I certainly hope that I wouldn’t. Certainly, I believe strongly that the wealthiest people in society have a greater responsibility. But that doesn’t mean I don’t have any – I can quite clearly make a difference, so I should.

      ‘So long as billionaires exist at the top society, so will the millions at the bottom.’

      Maybe, if you’re talking in strict terms about ‘power structures’. But if you’re talking about providing medicine, food and shelter to people who need them, the number of billionaires is kind of irrelevant. Singer’s point is politically independent. Whether you think you need to destroy the hierarchies in society or not, if you can help someone at no great cost to yourself, you should.

      Once again, if that child asked for a dollar for deworming medicine, would you answer, ‘No, I’m afraid I can’t give the money, because you would still be among the most marginalised people in the world’? I hope I wouldn’t.

      And once again, of course billionaires have a much greater responsibility than I do. But that doesn’t mean I don’t have any.

      ‘By viewing a certain section of society as ‘the poor’, this creates a category of a voiceless mass who have no option but to receive aid from kindly, morally upright strangers’.

      Certain people in the world don’t have enough money to live on, and recognising that fact isn’t some psychological ploy. If you want to change the language, do, but it doesn’t mean you shouldn’t also give them money. Recognising it also doesn’t change whether or not people have voices. The poorest in the world are generally voiceless, but that’s not because people call them poor.

      And I really don’t understand the ‘no option’ bit. Are you saying that we shouldn’t save the lives of the poorest people in the world, because to do so would make us feel superior? Because I really don’t think that people giving to the Against Malaria Foundation think of themselves as superior to the people who benefit from the Malaria nets, though maybe they do to the other Westerners who don’t don’t. But in any case, even if the strongest version of your claim is true, I’m pretty sure it’s more important that you save someone’s life than that you don’t feel superior to them.

      ‘what these elites contribute to society are more workers who buy into the concept of capitalism and self-reliance, who will nevertheless stay at the bottom of the pyramid – hence why I find that charity often reinforces divisions between the rich and poor rather than contributing to meaningful change – which is why the system of ‘philanthrocapitalism’ is so problematic to me.’

      This seems like a critique of the particular kind of NGO you say you were looking at (i.e. ones that encourage entrepreneurship), rather than Singer’s point, so if you disapprove in general of helping people start businesses, wouldn’t you just prefer to give to other charities that don’t do that?

      Overall:

      It seems like you want a political solution of some sort – you want to get rid of billionaires, at least. But do you not think that until this solution happens, or if it doesn’t at all, Singer’s argument still stands? If you can help save lives at minimal cost to yourself, you should. And since you can, you should.

      Moreover, I don’t see what this political solution is. The conditions in Bangladesh that Singer was writing in response to were partly a result of civil war and natural disaster. There weren’t any billionaires in Bangladesh at the time. You can eat the rich all you want (and Singer is indeed a proponent of a wealth tax), but if countries remain separate, the solutions to global poverty and poor health are always going to involve either direct aid or the kind of economic development projects you also object to.

      Emil

      1. Thanks for giving a proper counter to Audrey, Emil! I was well aware that I couldn’t truly do justice to Singer’s views, being acquainted with them only from a certain distance.

    2. The thing I take away from Singer is that he makes clear a certain contradiction in our world that would otherwise be largely hidden. We generally think that we are good and doing our bit, but Singer points out that clearly we could be doing a lot more without any significant inconvenience. Still, we do nothing, because the inconvenience is real as it requires change in ourselves and in society (to promote charity as a duty, rather than an extra good). This forces us either to say that our generally-if-unconsciously-held utilitarian worldview, that the thing to do is the thing that does the most good for the most people, is not the thing we actually find ourselves guided by. And if that is the case, then we must ask ourselves what actually does guide our actions. And this is generally frightening, because we find ourselves in a principleless, valueless, wasteland with nothing to hold on to. So we’d better not ask.

      Either we admit our worldview isn’t quite right, or we admit we’re not up to following it. Both of these are unpleasant.

      While I often find rich people intolerable, I think Singer’s ideas are not useless even if they cannot directly change systems. The need for people to have principles and a sense of duty is essential to improving the world. The distance between thinking that you should give up a little bit of money and that you should improve the world systematically is much smaller than the distance between doing nothing and giving a little. This is equally true of both the powerful and the weak. When I spent two weeks in the summer in America conversing exclusively with people who had a net worth in the tens or hundreds of millions of dollars the thing that struck me most was the complete absence of any sense of responsibility whatsoever.

      Responsibility can begin with Singer. That’s already something, even if we disagree about the particular form that he suggests it should take.

      Russia is always interesting. At the moment it is disheartening and desperately sad too.

Leave a Reply